少点错误 2024年09月04日
Democracy beyond majoritarianism
index_new5.html
../../../zaker_core/zaker_tpl_static/wap/tpl_guoji1.html

 

文章探讨民主制度,认为民主应是优化社会系统以满足所有人的平均偏好,还讨论了如何解决‘一般利益’的定义问题、直接民主的问题、政府的作用以及一些非多数原则决策的情况。

🎯民主不应只是多数人的统治,而应是优化社会系统以满足所有人的平均偏好,这是一种伦理原则,制度应以此来评判。

📚在Arrow不可能定理后,通过多种投票方式和相关选举,如Casella提出的可存储投票机制等,可解决一般利益的定义问题。

👨‍⚖️政治决策并非顺序独立,存在政策协同问题,因此需要政府。议会在某些可分离的决策上,应采用平均或排名投票等非多数原则。

🌐以NGO补贴分配、基础设施支出、司法提名、公共媒体控制等为例,说明非多数原则决策的应用及好处。

Published on September 3, 2024 3:10 PM GMT

The classical definition of democracy is “rule of majority with respect to the minority”. But the classics perfectly knew how oppressive can be the 51% of people over the rest and how difficult is to implement “respect”. I simply reject the majoritarian principle: democracy shall be about the rule of all, that is about optimizing the social system for the average of all preferences. More or less hard to implement, that is the ethical principle, and institutions shall be judged by that principle. 

In the second section of this article, I summarize how the concept of “general interest” can be rescued after the Arrow impossibility result. In the third section I comment on the problems of direct democracy, and why parliaments need to delegate to a unitary government the administration of the State (that is, why majoritarianism is to some extent still inevitable). And in the final section of this note I move into practical politics, proposing some cases where parliaments shall decide by “averaging” instead of by majority, and ask the gentle reader to expand my proposed list, because averaging and sortition are often better (and no less legitimate) than majority rule.

The general interest

In decision theory textbooks a famous result (the “Arrow impossibility theorem”, Arrow, 1951) suggests that the general interest is impossible even to be defined. But a theorem is not a truth about external reality, but a truth about a given formal system. The Arrow theorem is true if preferences are ordinal and there is a single election. With cardinal preferences and multiple votes there is no “impossibility” theorem. 

Suppose there is a set of “attainable” states of the Word X. Naive cardinal utilitarianism suggest that given an aggregation function W(.) -often simply a sum- and J members of the society each with a (possibly different) utility cardinal function on the states of the World, the social optimum is simply the point (attainable state of the world) that maximizes aggregate utility:

Unfortunately, this kind of optimization depends on absolute level of utility: more “sensitive” individuals (those whose utility function are cardinally larger) are given more “rights” under “cardinal utilitarianism”, but there is no way to know who is more sensitive because consciousness is noumenal. As long as the absolute levels of utility matter, utilitarianism is between wrong and simply useless (it depends on the deepest unobservable).

To deal with this, we shall recognize that interpersonal utility comparison is a political decision. In the modern democratic world, our main constitutional choice is the “one man, one vote” principle: in utilitarian parlance we suppose all people are equally sensitive and equally valuable and equal political rights are given to all. This supposition implies first “utility normalization” (Dhillon, Bouveret Lemaître, 1999), and only after utility normalization aggregate welfare maximization

In practice, for a single vote, the Arrow theorem perchlorates into the “cardinal normalized preferences” framework because in a single election there is no way you can signal preference intensity. The escape from Arrow impossibility (as was already suggested in Buchanan, 1962) depends on multiple and related elections (Casella and Macè, 2021).

Casella (2005) proposed the Storable Votes (SV) voting mechanism, where participants in a sequence of elections are given additional votes in each period, so they can signal the intensity of their preferences and avoid the disenfranchisement of minorities that comes from simple majority voting. Shortly after the introduction of SV, Jackson & Sonnenschein (2007) proved that connecting decisions over time can resolve the issue of incentive compatibility in a broad range of social choice problems. 

Macias (2024a) proposed the “Storable Votes-Pay as you win” (SV-PAYW) mechanism where a fixed number of storable votes are used to decide on a sequence of elections, but only votes casted on the winning alternative are withdrawn from the vote accounts of each player (and those wining votes are equally redistributed among all participants). In a simulation environment this kind of “auction like” version of the SV mechanism allowed for minority view integration into the democratic process with only a very modest deviation from social optimality.  

Why government?

If political decisions were sequential and independent, SV-PAYW probably (we have no theorems, only numerical simulations) would solve the preference aggregation problem, and Arrow’s problem could be considered overcame with no need of government (assembly rule, either direct or representative would be efficient). Unfortunately, political decisions are far from “sequential and independent”. Portfolios of policies have synergies and independent choice of policies can lead to suboptimal outcomes.  That is why assembly rule is unusual and parliaments always appoint a government. It also explains why SV-PAYW was not discovered and applied centuries ago. 

In the “Ideal Political Workflow” (Macias, 2024b), I suggested that in the perfect democracy, people would vote in the space of “outcomes” not in the space of “policies”, avoiding by that expedient the “political coherence problem”, but that is only possible if the relation between “policies” and “outcomes” is well known. Unfortunately, often matters of fact are politicized and/or are not well understood. 

For the time being, the Ideal Political Workflow will remain… ideal.

Separable decisions and non-majoritarian rules 

But sometimes decisions are separable. For example, decisions on private consumption are so separable that we can leave them mostly to households and firms (that is the meaning of the two theorems on welfare economics).

For some separable decisions, in my view parliaments shall decide not by majority, but by averaging (or rank voting). 

Averaging gives power to every single MP, avoiding minority disenfranchisement. Now, gentle reader, what else? What other issues shall a Parliament decide by average/ranked voting/sharing instead of by majority and which concrete rule do you favor?

 

References

Arrow, K.J. (1951). Social Choice and Individual Values. New York: Wiley,

Buchanan, J.M. (1962). The Calculus of Consent. Ann Arbor: Univ.Mich.Press 

Casella, A. (2005). Storable Votes, Games and Economic Behavior. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.geb.2004.09.009

Casella, A., Macè, A. (2021). Does Vote Trading Improve Welfare?, Annual Review of Economics. https://doi.org/10.1146/annurev-economics-081720-114422

Dhillon, A., Bouveret, S.,Lemaître, M. (1999). Relative Utilitarianism. Econometricahttps://doi.org/10.1111/1468-0262.00033

Jackson M.O.,Sonnenschein H.F. (2007). Overcoming incentive constraints by linking decisions, Econometrica. https://doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0262.2007.00737.x

Macías, A. (2024a). Storable votes with a pay-as-you-win mechanism, Journal of Economic Interaction and Coordination. Ungated version: https://papers.ssrn.com/sol3/papers.cfm?abstract_id=4326247

Macías, A. (2024b). The Ideal Political workflow. SSRN 



Discuss

Fish AI Reader

Fish AI Reader

AI辅助创作,多种专业模板,深度分析,高质量内容生成。从观点提取到深度思考,FishAI为您提供全方位的创作支持。新版本引入自定义参数,让您的创作更加个性化和精准。

FishAI

FishAI

鱼阅,AI 时代的下一个智能信息助手,助你摆脱信息焦虑

联系邮箱 441953276@qq.com

相关标签

民主制度 非多数原则 政治决策 利益优化
相关文章