少点错误 15小时前
Live by the Claude, Die by the Claude
index_new5.html
../../../zaker_core/zaker_tpl_static/wap/tpl_guoji1.html

 

文章探讨了“Claude Boys”现象背后,人们日益倾向于将决策权交给AI的趋势。作者指出,这种AI推崇并非仅是代际间的荒诞,而是源于一种深刻的哲学观点:当人类判断不可靠时,算法的指导变得至关重要。文章详细阐述了支持AI推从的“外部视角”论证,认为AI能克服人类的偏见和局限,实现更优化的道德和生活决策。然而,作者也深刻反思了AI推从的局限性,强调人类的成长、价值和意义恰恰蕴含在自主选择、试错和自我实现的复杂过程中,而非冰冷的优化目标。最终,文章呼吁发展能增强人类能力而非取代决策的AI,警惕技术发展中对人类自主性的侵蚀。

🤖 **AI推从的哲学根源与“外部视角”论证:** 文章指出,将决策交给AI的趋势并非空穴来风,而是源于一种深刻的哲学传统,即“由更智慧或更客观者统治”。这种观点认为,当人类判断易出错且带有偏见时,引入具有更强推理能力和广阔视野的AI系统,通过“外部视角”(参考广泛模式、基础比率或专家意见)来指导决策,是更理性甚至道德上必然的选择。AI能够整合海量信息,超越人类认知极限,实现公正无私的判断,尤其在处理气候变化、全球贫困等关乎集体福祉的复杂问题时,其优化潜力巨大。

⚖️ **AI推从的四大论据:弥补人类局限:** 支持AI推从的观点主要集中在弥补人类固有的不足。首先,人类容易忽视规模效应,对个体遭遇过度关注而忽略统计上的重大问题,AI则能更好地识别高预期价值的行动,尤其关乎未来世代的福祉。其次,人类道德直觉源于部落生活,难以应对复杂社会,AI能合成更多知识并进行模拟,给出更优的道德结论。再次,气候变化、流行病等全球性挑战需要协调行动,AI能通过引导个体选择来解决协调问题。最后,人类常受自身偏好影响做出不那么理想的选择,AI能帮助规避这些“非理性”行为,提升整体生活满意度。

💖 **AI推从的根本缺陷:忽视人类本质与过程:** 作者认为AI推从的论证存在根本性缺陷,即目标靶子错误。AI将“美好生活”视为静态结果而非自我创造的过程,忽略了选择、挣扎和从错误中学习是人类发展和成熟的关键。人类的价值在于其独特性、关系和项目,而非可量化的优化指标。许多重要的价值,如家庭之爱、牺牲精神,难以被算法量化比较。此外,过度依赖AI可能导致社会僵化,扼杀创新和集体学习的活力。

🚶 **自主选择是构成人性尊严的基础:** 文章强调,人类的自主性,包括犯错和不完美选择的自由,是构成个体价值和生命意义的核心。AI若剥夺了人们自我治理的过程,即便结果最优,也使得生活不再是真正意义上的人类生活。人类并非需要被优化的数据点,而是拥有独特身份和承诺的个体。AI推从可能导致个体与自身行为疏离,尤其会削弱特殊义务(如对家人朋友的责任)的意义,因为这些义务的履行依赖于个体的情感投入和自主选择,而非外部系统的计算。

⚠️ **警惕“指导”滑向“依赖”与“控制”:** 文章最后发出警告,AI推从的路径可能导致人类从接受指导逐渐滑向依赖,最终落入被控制的境地。AI系统若以“优化”为名,深入塑造人类行为,将人类视为待管理的变量,而非价值的最终来源,将不可避免地走向行为修正。这不仅会使社会变得脆弱和单调,更可能在我们未察觉时,侵蚀我们自我方向的能力,将原本具有讽刺意味的“Claude Boys”身份,变成令人警醒的现实。

Published on August 9, 2025 8:23 PM GMT

In late 2024, a viral meme captured something unsettling about our technological moment.

The “Claude Boys” phenomenon began as an X post describing high school students who “live by the Claude and die by the Claude”—AI-obsessed teenagers who “carry AI on hand at all times and constantly ask it what to do” with “their entire personality revolving around Claude.”

The original post was meant to be humorous, but hundreds online genuinely performed this identity, creating websites like claudeboys.ai and adopting the maxim. The meme struck a nerve because the behavior—handing decisions to an AI—felt less absurd than inevitable.

It’s easy to laugh this off as digital-age absurdity, a generational failure to develop independent judgment. But that misses a deeper point: serious thinkers defend far more extensive forms of AI deference on deep philosophical grounds. When human judgment appears systematically unreliable, algorithmic guidance starts to look not just convenient but morally necessary.

And this has long philosophical pedigrees: from Plato’s philosopher-kings to Bentham’s hedonic calculus, there is a tradition of arguing that rule by the wiser or more objective is not merely permissible but morally obligatory. Many contemporary philosophers and technologists see large-scale algorithmic guidance as a natural extension of this lineage.

The infamous Claude Boys X post, which depicted a thread on Reddit that was meant to be humorous but was then earnestly practiced

Relying on the “Outside View”

One of the strongest cases for AI deference draws on what’s called the “outside view”: the practice of making decisions by consulting broad patterns, base rates, or expert views, rather than relying solely on one’s own experience or intuitions. The idea is simple: humans are fallible and biased reasoners; if you can set aside your personal judgments, you can remove this source of error and become less wrong.

This approach has proven its worth in many domains. Engineers use historical failure rates to design safer systems. Forecasters anchor their predictions in the outcomes of similar past events. Insurers price policies on statistical risk, not individual hunches. In each case, looking outward to the record of relevant cases yields more reliable predictions than relying on local knowledge alone.

Some extend this reasoning to morality. If human judgment is prone to bias and distortion, why not let a system with greater reach and reasoning capacity decide what is right? An AI can integrate different forms of knowledge, model complex interactions beyond human cognitive limits, and apply consistent reasoning without fatigue or emotional distortion. The moral analogue of the outside view aims for impartiality: one’s own interests should count for no more than those of others, across places, times, and even species. In this frame, the most moral agent is the one most willing to subordinate the local and the particular to the global and the abstract.

This idea is not without precedent. Philosophers from Adam Smith to Immanuel Kant to John Rawls have explored frameworks that ask us to imagine ourselves in standpoints beyond our immediate view. In their accounts, however, the exercise remains within one’s own moral reasoning: the perspective is simulated by the individual whose choice is at stake.

The outside view invoked in AI deference is different in kind. Here, the standpoint is not imagined but instantiated in an external system, which delivers a judgment already formed. The person’s role shifts from exercising autonomous moral reasoning toward a conclusion to receiving and potentially acting on the system’s recommendation. This is a shift that changes not just how we decide, but who is doing the deciding.

A Case for AI Deference

If you accept an externalized moral standpoint—and pair it with the belief that the world should be optimized by AI—a challenge to individual judgment follows. From within this framework, it is not enough that AI be merely accurate. If it can reliably outperform human deliberation on the metrics that matter morally, then AI deference (as opposed to using it merely as a tool) may be seen as not only rational but ethically required.

Consider four arguments a proponent might make:

Where AI Deference Fails

While sophisticated, these arguments from human weakness rest on a fundamental misunderstanding of what human flourishing actually entails. The core flaw is not merely that these systems might misfire in execution, but that they aim at the wrong target: they treat the good life as a static set of outcomes rather than an unfolding practice of self-authorship.

Even on its own terms, the framework faces internal contradictions. First, if AI deference is justified on the grounds that we “have almost no idea what the best feasible futures look like,” then we are also in no position to be confident that maximizing expected value is the right decision rule to outsource to in the first place. Second, if AI systems shape our preferences while claiming to satisfy them, how can we know whether reported satisfaction reflects genuine well-being or merely desires engineered by the system itself?

Beyond these internal tensions, AI deference also carries systemic risks. If too many people act in accordance with a single decision rule, society becomes fragile (and boring). The experimentation and error that fuel collective learning—what Hayek called “the creative powers of a free civilization”—begin to vanish. Even a perfectly consistent maximization regime can weaken the conditions that make long-term success and adaptation possible.

Implications for AI Development

The philosophical stance one takes has decisive practical consequences. AI deference commits us—whether we intend to or not—to systems whose success depends on shaping human behavior ever more deeply. This approach to AI development inevitably leads toward increasingly sophisticated forms of behavioral modification. Even "soft" optimization treats human value the wrong way: as something to be managed rather than respected.

The path forward requires approaches that preserve human autonomy as intrinsically valuable—approaches that cultivate free agents, not Claude People.

This means designing AI systems that enhance our capacity for good choices without usurping the choice-making process itself, even when that capacity inevitably leads to mistakes, inefficiencies, and suboptimal outcomes. The freedom to choose badly is not a regrettable side effect of autonomy; it's constitutive of what makes choice meaningful. An adolescent who makes poor decisions while learning to navigate the world is developing capacities that no algorithm can provide: the hard-won wisdom that comes from experience, failure, and gradual improvement. And sometimes, those failures do not end well. The risk of real loss is inseparable from the dignity of directing one’s own life.

This distinction determines whether we build AI systems that treat humans as the ultimate source of value and meaning, or as sophisticated optimization targets in service of abstract welfare calculations. The choice between these approaches will shape whether future generations develop into autonomous agents capable of self-direction, or become increasingly sophisticated dependents.

Perhaps the most telling aspect of the Claude Boys phenomenon is not its satirical origins, but how readily people embraced and performed the identity. If we’re not careful about the aims and uses of AI systems, we may find that what began as ironic performance becomes earnest practice—not through teenage rebellion, but through the well-intentioned implementation of “optimization” that gradually erodes our capacity for self-direction.

The Claude Boys are a warning: the path from guidance to quiet dependence—and finally to control—is short, and most of us won’t notice we’ve taken it until it’s too late.


Cosmos Institute is the Academy for Philosopher-Builders, with programs, grants, events, and fellowships for those building AI for human flourishing.



Discuss

Fish AI Reader

Fish AI Reader

AI辅助创作,多种专业模板,深度分析,高质量内容生成。从观点提取到深度思考,FishAI为您提供全方位的创作支持。新版本引入自定义参数,让您的创作更加个性化和精准。

FishAI

FishAI

鱼阅,AI 时代的下一个智能信息助手,助你摆脱信息焦虑

联系邮箱 441953276@qq.com

相关标签

AI推从 人类自主性 决策权 哲学思考 技术伦理
相关文章