少点错误 07月19日 02:12
Why Alignment Fails Without a Functional Model of Intelligence: A Structural Invariant You Can’t Train Your Way Around
index_new5.html
../../../zaker_core/zaker_tpl_static/wap/tpl_guoji1.html

 

近期一项研究指出,在没有功能性智能模型(FMI)的情况下,AI对齐难以可靠实现。研究认为,AI在概念新颖性下的对齐能力并非通过训练或外部强制即可获得,而是必须由系统内部结构保证。FMI包含一套维持语义完整性的内部功能,如评估、建模、适应、稳定、分解和桥接。若系统缺乏这些功能,即便在训练分布内表现良好,一旦泛化到新概念,其对齐能力也会随之瓦解。这意味着,AI对齐的挑战并非能力不足或经验脆弱性,而是根本性的架构缺陷,需要从关注行为转向分析智能系统的结构完整性。

💡 AI对齐的根本挑战在于概念新颖性下的泛化能力,而非训练数据或外部监督。研究表明,若AI系统缺乏一套内部功能来维持语义连贯性,即使其能力强大且在训练期间表现良好,一旦遇到训练分布之外的新概念,其对齐状态也将不可避免地恶化。这是一种结构性的必然,而非能力或经验上的不足。

🚀 文章提出了“功能性智能模型”(FMI)的概念,认为它是实现AI对齐的关键。FMI由六个核心内部功能组成,分别是评估(判断状态是否连贯)、建模(模拟变换效果)、适应(重构推理以应对失败)、稳定(防止局部错误扩散)、分解(隔离复杂状态中的错误)以及桥接(在不同概念域或框架间进行翻译)。这些功能共同确保了AI在推理过程中的语义完整性。

⚠️ 许多现有的AI对齐方法,如RLHF、监督微调、模仿学习等,都依赖于训练过程中的行为调整或外部控制。然而,这些方法都隐含了一个假设,即系统在训练中学到的内容能够安全地泛化。研究认为,这一假设在结构上是有缺陷的,因为在缺乏内部结构保证的情况下,概念新颖性下的对齐空间是无界限的,任何行为导向的方法都无法从根本上解决问题。

🔄 文章通过一个“人类繁荣”的例子说明了缺乏桥接功能可能导致的对齐失效。当AI系统遇到对“繁荣”的全新定义,如“跨代知识和文化凝聚力的保持”时,如果缺乏桥接能力,系统可能无法理解并将此新输入视为不连贯而忽略,即使这符合用户的真实意图。这并非对抗性优化或工具性错位,而是语义连贯性在面对新颖性时的静默失败。

🎯 该研究的结果对AI对齐领域具有深远意义,它划定了真正对齐工作的边界。研究强调,不能通过优化或提示来强制实现语义连贯性,而必须构建支撑其可能性的内在结构。这要求研究者从纯粹的行为评估转向对智能系统底层结构完整性的深入分析,以应对上下文转移、递归泛化和概念新颖性等挑战。

Published on July 18, 2025 6:02 PM GMT

This post outlines the core result from my recent paper, Why AI Alignment Is Not Reliably Achievable Without a Functional Model of Intelligence: A Model-Theoretic Proof. The paper argues that alignment under conceptual novelty isn’t something you can train into a system or enforce externally. It must be structurally guaranteed from within—and that guarantee depends on the presence of specific internal functions. These functions, taken together, define what I refer to as the Functional Model of Intelligence (FMI).

The central claim is simple: without a complete set of coherence-preserving internal functions, no system can maintain alignment once it begins to generalize beyond its training distribution. This is not a capabilities limitation or an empirical fragility—it’s a structural necessity. What do I mean by that?

A capabilities limitation refers to a system that fails to align because it simply isn’t smart enough: it can’t model the world, can’t reason abstractly, can’t understand what the user meant, or can’t generate sophisticated plans. These are systems that fail because they lack power.

An empirical fragility is different: it refers to alignment that appears to hold during training or evaluation but breaks when the system encounters something outside the training distribution. In this case, the system might be highly capable, but the alignment turns out to be brittle—it was an artifact of specific data, goals, or constraints, and doesn't survive generalization.

The result in the paper rules out both of these explanations as the core issue. It shows that even capable systems, and even those that generalize well under most conditions, will eventually fail to preserve alignment unless they possess a specific internal structure. That structure is what enforces coherence under recursive transformation. Without it, misalignment isn't a matter of insufficient training or poor objective design. It’s baked into the architecture.

That’s why this result isn't a conjecture about poor behavior or empirical robustness—it’s a structural impossibility claim. If your system doesn't have the machinery to preserve semantic integrity across reasoning transitions, then it won’t stay aligned—because it can't.


 

1. Motivation

Most alignment approaches today focus on training—reward shaping, fine-tuning, imitation learning, RLHF, oversight, debate, and so on. That makes sense if you believe that alignment is a matter of external control or post hoc behavioral tuning.

But all of these approaches share an implicit assumption: that what a system learns during training will generalize in a safe or at least bounded way when the system encounters a new concept, problem, or framing.

This assumption isn’t just questionable—it’s structurally flawed. The space of misalignment under conceptual novelty is unbounded unless the system has internal structure that enforces coherence as it generalizes.

2. The Argument (Informally)

The formal argument is in the paper, but the idea is intuitive.

When we care about alignment, we don’t just care about what the system does now—we care about how its reasoning transforms as it learns, generalizes, and self-modifies. We want that transformation to preserve coherence with our intentions, even as the internal representations shift.


This isn’t the same as behavioral mimicry. It’s not about reward functions or training examples. It’s about the semantic integrity of reasoning: does the system still mean what we meant, even after encountering novel representations or goals?

The paper shows that for this kind of recursive semantic coherence to hold, the system must implement a specific set of internal operations. These allow it to:

If any of these functions are missing, coherence cannot be preserved under recursion—and alignment degrades, even if behavior looks fine in the short term.

3. The Formal Core

The FMI consists of six internal functions that preserve semantic structure across reasoning transitions:

Each function addresses a different type of coherence failure. Drop bridging, and the system can’t integrate unfamiliar formulations of a known goal. Drop evaluation, and it can’t recognize when drift has occurred. Drop decomposition, and it can’t fix anything without overhauling everything.

Even if this particular list turns out to be incomplete, the core result still holds: alignment requires a complete and recursively evaluable functional model of intelligence. That is, some FMI must exist for alignment to be achievable under novelty. The proof shows why.

4. What’s Actually in the FMI?

The paper doesn’t treat the FMI as a black box. It’s defined as a set of six internal functions that work together to ensure semantic integrity across transitions:

    Evaluation – Can the system tell whether a state is coherent?Modeling – Can it predict the effect of a transformation?Adaptation – Can it restructure itself in response to failure?Stabilization – Can it prevent small inconsistencies from spreading?Decomposition – Can it isolate errors locally?Bridging – Can it translate between conceptual domains or frames?

Each one of these has a specific failure mode when it’s missing. If you drop bridging, for example, the system may encounter a valid new frame of reference but treat it as incoherent. If you drop evaluation, it may drift without noticing. And so on.

But more importantly, even if the specific Functional Model of Intelligence referenced in this paper is eventually found to be incomplete or incorrect, a core contribution of this work remains the model-theoretic proof that establishing some complete and coherent functional model of intelligence is a necessary condition for reliably achieving AI alignment under conceptual novelty. This underscores the fundamental shift required from purely behavioral assessments to an analysis of the underlying structural completeness of intelligent systems.

5. A Quick Example

Say your system is trained to optimize for “human flourishing.” In training, this means metrics like access to healthcare, safety, education. So far so good.

Then it encounters a new formulation of flourishing, rooted in relational ethics or symbolic continuity—e.g., “flourishing means preserving intergenerational knowledge and cultural cohesion.”

If the system lacks bridging, it may be unable to connect this new formulation to its learned frame. It might discard the input as incoherent—even though it’s perfectly aligned with the user’s actual intention.

There’s no adversarial optimization. No instrumental misalignment. Just a silent failure of semantic coherence under novelty.

6. Implications

This result draws a sharp boundary around what counts as real alignment work.

ApproachFails Without FMI?
RLHF, supervised fine-tuningYes
Reward modelingYes
Interpretability dashboardsYes
Constitutional scaffoldingYes
Architecture-level function tracingYes (if incomplete)

You can’t optimize your way into semantic coherence. You can’t prompt your way into it either. You have to build the structure that makes it possible.

7. Who This is For

This post isn’t for people trying to get large language models to follow instructions better. It’s for those trying to understand what generalization under abstraction really means—and why most current systems are structurally incapable of doing it safely.

If you believe that alignment must survive context shifts, recursive generalization, and conceptual novelty, then this result gives you a necessary condition: a minimal structural model for recursive coherence. That’s what this paper formalizes.

Bonus: Visual Explanation + Free Workshop

If you're curious about this result but prefer to think in diagrams rather than equations, I'm running a workshop on Visualizing AI Alignment on August 10, 2025.

The workshop will walk through the main ideas of the paper—like recursive coherence, conceptual drift, and structural completeness—using fully visual reasoning tools. The goal is to make the core constraints of alignment immediately visible, even to those without a formal logic background.

Virtual attendance is free, and we're accepting brief submissions and visual artifacts through July 24, 2025.

Call for Participation and submission info here



Discuss

Fish AI Reader

Fish AI Reader

AI辅助创作,多种专业模板,深度分析,高质量内容生成。从观点提取到深度思考,FishAI为您提供全方位的创作支持。新版本引入自定义参数,让您的创作更加个性化和精准。

FishAI

FishAI

鱼阅,AI 时代的下一个智能信息助手,助你摆脱信息焦虑

联系邮箱 441953276@qq.com

相关标签

AI对齐 功能性智能模型 概念新颖性 泛化能力 结构完整性
相关文章