未知数据源 2024年10月02日
Paradigm shifts: positivism, realism and the fight against apathy in the quantum revolution
index_new5.html
../../../zaker_core/zaker_tpl_static/wap/tpl_guoji1.html

 

文章探讨了量子革命中的各种观点和争论。包括玻尔的量子理论、爱因斯坦的不同看法,以及相关的各种解释和争议。还提到了凯的观点及他对一些历史神话的深化,以及现代物理学家对量子理论基础的态度等。

🦘玻尔认为量子理论是用从经典物理学中窃取的概念来描述根本上具有统计性的量子世界,概率的计算是我们能期望的最好结果,且此理论的哥本哈根解释曾被指责为实证主义。

🚀爱因斯坦不同意玻尔的观点,他探索更符合实在论形而上学的替代方案,认为对物理世界的有效知识应源于直接经验,玻尔与爱因斯坦的辩论至今仍未解决。

💥凯在其著作中坚定地站在爱因斯坦的角落,通过选择性解读科学史来构建论点,认为哥本哈根学派是一个以玻尔为中心的人格崇拜团体。

🌐战后美国化的物理学将关于量子理论意义的哲学问题边缘化,多数物理学家只关注计算,而不关心理论的意义,这种正统观念实际上更多是社会学的,而非哲学的。

🎯凯认为量子流体动力学类似实验表明,德布罗意的导波解释应得到更多关注,但该解释存在非局部性问题,且凯试图利用的贝尔定理漏洞已被大量实验关闭。

Science can be a messy business. Scientists caught in the storm of a scientific revolution will try to react with calm logic and reasoning. But in a revolution the stakes are high, the atmosphere charged. Cherished concepts are abandoned as troubling new notions are cautiously embraced. And, as the paradigm shifts, the practice of science is overlaid with passionate advocacy and open hostility in near-equal measure. So it was – and, to a large extent, still is – with the quantum revolution.

Niels Bohr insisted that quantum theory is the result of efforts to describe a fundamentally statistical quantum world using concepts stolen from classical physics, which must therefore be interpreted “symbolically”. The calculation of probabilities, with no reference to any underlying causal mechanism that might explain how they arise, is the best we can hope for.

In the heat of the quantum revolution, Bohr’s “Copenhagen interpretation” was accused of positivism, the philosophy that valid knowledge of the physical world is derived only from direct experience. Albert Einstein famously disagreed, taking the time to explore alternatives more in keeping with a realist metaphysics, with a “trust in the rational character of reality and in its being accessible, to some extent, to human reason”, that had served science for centuries. Lest there be any doubt, Adam Forrest Kay’s Escape from Shadow Physics: the Quest to End the Dark Ages of Quantum Theory demonstrates that the Bohr–Einstein debate remains unresolved, at least to anybody’s satisfaction, and continues to this day.

Escape from Shadow Physics is a singular addition to the popular literature on quantum interpretations. Kay holds PhDs in both literature and mathematics and is currently a mathematics postdoc at the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. He stands firmly in Einstein’s corner, and his plea for a return to a realist programme is liberally sprinkled with passionate advocacy and open hostility in near-equal measure. He writes with the zeal of a true quantum reactionary.

Like many others before him, in arguing his case Kay needs first to build a monstrous, positivist Goliath that can be slain with the slingshot of realist logic and reasoning. This means embracing some enduring historical myths. These run as follows. The Bohr–Einstein debate was a direct confrontation between the subjectivism of the positivist and the objectivism of the realist. Bohr won the debate by browbeating the stubborn, senile and increasingly isolated Einstein into submission. Acting like some fanatical priesthood, physicists of Bohr’s church – such as Wolfgang Pauli, Werner Heisenberg and Léon Rosenfeld – shouted down all dissent, establishing the Copenhagen interpretation as a dogmatic orthodoxy.

Historical scientific myths are not entirely wrong, and typically hold some grains of truth. Rivals to the Copenhagen view were indeed given short shrift by the “Copenhagen hegemony”. Pauli sought to dismantle Louis de Broglie’s “pilot wave” interpretation soon after it was presented in 1927. He went on to dismiss its rediscovery by David Bohm in 1952 as “shadow physics beer-idea wish dreams”, and “not even new nonsense”. Rosenfeld dismissed Hugh Everett III’s “many worlds” interpretation of 1957 as “hopelessly wrong ideas”.

But Kay is not content with the myth as it is familiarly told, and so seeks to deepen it. He confers on Bohr “the charisma of the hypnotist, the charisma of the cult leader”, adding that “the Copenhagen group was, in a very real sense, a personality cult, centred on the special and wise Bohr”. Prosecuting such a case requires a selective reading of science history, snatching quotations where they fit the narrative, ignoring others where they don’t. In fact, Bohr did not deny objective reality, or the reality of electrons and atoms. In interviews conducted shortly before his death in 1962, Bohr reaffirmed that his core principle of “complementarity” (of waves and particles, for example) was “the only possible objective description”. Heisenberg, in contrast, was much less cautious in his use of language and makes an easier target for anti-positivist ire.

It can be argued that the orthodoxy, such as it is, is not actually based on philosophical pre-commitments. The post-war Americanization of physics drove what were judged to be pointless philosophical questions about the meaning of quantum theory to the fringes. Aside from those few physicists and philosophers who continued to nag at the problem, the majority of physicists just got on with their calculations, completely unconcerned about what the theory was supposed to mean. They just didn’t care.

As Bohm explained: “Everybody plays lip service to Bohr, but nobody knows what he says. People then get brainwashed into saying Bohr is right, but when the time comes to do their physics, they are doing something different.” Many who might claim to follow Bohr’s “dogma” satisfy their physical intuitions by continuing to think like Einstein.

Anton Zeilinger, who shared the 2022 Nobel Prize for Physics for his work on quantum entanglement and quantum information science, confessed that even physicists working in this new field consider foundations to be a bit dodgy: “We don’t understand the reason why. Must be psychological reasons, something like that, something very deep.” Kay admits this much when he writes: “Yes, many people think the debate is over and Bohr won, but that is actually a social phenomenon.” In other words, the orthodoxy is not philosophical, it is sociological. It has very little to do with Bohr and the Copenhagen interpretation. In truth, Kay is fighting for attention against the apathy and indifference characteristic of an orthodox mainstream physics, or what Thomas Kuhn called “normal science”.

As to how a modern-day realist programme might be pursued, Kay treats us to some visually suggestive experiments in which oil droplets follow trajectories determined by wave disturbances on the surface of the oil bath on which they move. He argues that such “quantum hydrodynamic analogues” show us that the pilot-wave interpretation merits much more attention than it has so far received. But while these analogues are intuitively appealing, the so-called “quantization” involved is as familiarly classical as musical notes generated by string or wind instruments. And, although such analogues may conjure surprising trajectories and patterns, they cannot conjure Planck’s constant. Or quantum entanglement.

But the pilot-wave interpretation demands a hefty trade-off. It features precisely the non-local, “peculiar mechanism of action at a distance” of the kind that Einstein abhorred, and which discouraged his own exploration of pilot waves in 1927. In an attempt to rescue the possibility that reality may yet be local, Kay reaches for a loophole in John Bell’s famous theorem and inequality. Yet he overlooks the enormous volume and variety of experiments that have been performed since the early 1980s, including tests of an inequality devised by the Nobel-prize-winning theorist Anthony Leggett that explicitly close the loophole he seeks to exploit.

Escape from Shadow Physics is a curate’s egg. Those readers who would condemn Bohr and the Copenhagen interpretation, for whatever reasons of their own, will likely cheer it on. Those looking for balanced arguments more reasoned than diatribe will likely be disappointed. Despite an extensive bibliography, Kay commits some curious sins of omission. But, while the journey that Kay takes may be flawed, there is yet sympathy for his destination. The debate does remain unresolved. Faced with the mystery of entanglement and non-locality, Bohr’s philosophy offers no solace. Kay (quoting a popular textbook) asks that we consider future generations in possession of a more sophisticated theory, who wonder how we could have been so gullible.

The post Paradigm shifts: positivism, realism and the fight against apathy in the quantum revolution appeared first on Physics World.

Fish AI Reader

Fish AI Reader

AI辅助创作,多种专业模板,深度分析,高质量内容生成。从观点提取到深度思考,FishAI为您提供全方位的创作支持。新版本引入自定义参数,让您的创作更加个性化和精准。

FishAI

FishAI

鱼阅,AI 时代的下一个智能信息助手,助你摆脱信息焦虑

联系邮箱 441953276@qq.com

相关标签

量子革命 玻尔 爱因斯坦 量子理论
相关文章